Legend has it that Galileo tested Aristotle's theories of falling bodies a demonstation that all Europe could hear. He is supposed to have climbed to the top of the Leaning Tower of Pisa and simultaneously dropped two cannon balls, one ten times heavier than the other. The thump of the two balls hitting the ground in the same split second killed Aristotelian physics. This seems to be nothing more than legend but a similar experiment was actually formed, or at least described, some years earlier by the Belgian-Dutch mathematician, Simon Stevinus. But the story is so typical of Galileo's dramatic methods that it is no wonder it has been widely believed through the centuries.
Galileo undeniably did roll balls down inclined planes and measured the distance that they traveled in given times. He was the first to conduct time experiments and to use measurement in a systematic way. Since his methods for measuring time weren't accurate enough to follow the rate of motion of a body in free fall, he "diluted" gravity by allowing a body to roll down an inclined plane. By making the slope of the inclined plane a gentle one, he could slow the motion as much as he wished. It was then quite easy to show that the rate of fall of a body was quite independent of its weight. He was also able to show that a body moved along an inclined plane at a constantly accelerating velocity; that is, it moved more and more quickly. Leonardo da Vinci had noted this a century earlier but had kept it to himself. This settled an important philosophic point. Aristotle had held that in order to keep a body moving, a force had to be continually applied. From this it followed, according to some medieval philosophers, that the heavenly bodies, which were continually moving, had to be pushed along by the eternal labors of angels. A few even used such arguments to deduce the existence of God. On the other hand, some philosophers of the late Middle Ages, such as the French philosopher, Jean Buridan (c.1300-c.1385) held that constant motion required no force after the initial impulse. By that view God in creating the world could have given it a start and then let it run by itself forever after. If a continuous force were applied, said these philosophers, the resulting motion would become ever more rapid. Galileo's experiments decided in favor of this second view and against Aristotle. Not only did the velocity of a falling ball increase steadily with time under the continuous pull of the earth, but the total distance it covered increased as the square of the time. He also showed that a body could move under the influence of two forces at one time. One force, applying an initial force horizontally (as the explosion of a gun), could keep a body moving horizontally at a constant velocity. Another force, applied constantly in a vertical direction, could make the same body drop downward at an accelerated velocity. The two motions superimposed would cause the body to follow a parabolic curve. In this way Galileo was able to make a science out of gunnery. This concept of one body influenced by more than one force also explained how it was that everything on the surface of the earth, including the atmosphere, birds in flight, and falling stones, could share in Earth's rotation and yet maintain their superimposed motions. This disposed of one of the most effective arguments against the theories of Copernicus and showed that one need not fear that the turning and revolving earth would leave behind those objects not firmly attached to it. Galileo's proofs were all reached by the geometric methods of the Greeks. The application of algebra to geometry and the discovery of infinitely more powerful methods of mathematical analysis than those at Galileo's disposal had to await the French philosopher and mathematician, Renˇ Descartes (1596-1650), and the English physicist and mathematician, Isaac Newton. Yet Galileo made do with what he had and his discoveries marked the beginning of the science of mechanics and served as the basis a century later for the three laws of motion propounded by Newton.) In his book on mechanics Galileo also dealt with the strength of materials, founding that branch of science as well. He was the first to show that if a structure increased in all dimensions equally, it would grow weaker -- at least he was the first to explain the theoretical basis for this. This is what is now known as the square-cube law. The volume increases as the cube of linear dimensions but the strength only as the square. For that reason larger animals require proportionally sturdier supports than small ones. A deer expanded to the size of an elephant and kept in exact proportion would collapse. Its legs would have to be thickened out of proportion for proper support. The success of Galileo and his successors, particularly Newton, in accounting for motion by pushes and pulls ("forces") gave rise to the thought that everything in the universe capable of measurement could be explained on the basis of pushes and pulls no more complicated in essence than the pushes and pulls of levers and gears within a machine. This mechanistic view of the universe was to gain favor until a new revolution in science three centuries after Galileo showed matters to be rather more complicated than the mechanists had assumed. Yet Galileo was reluctant to denounce Aristotelian physics too publicly. He waited for a safe opportunity to do so and this came with the nova of 1604 (the one usually associated with Johann Kepler), Galileo used the nova to argue against the Aristotelian notion of the immutability of the heavens and, by implication, against the Aristotelian view generally. Galileo's work made him unpopular at Pisa and he moved to a better position at Padua, in Venetian territory. (Venice was a region of considerable intellectual freedom at that time.) The new position paid three times the salary of the old one -- though Galileo lived gaily and generously and was always in debt anyway. He was always in trouble, too, for he made himself unpopular with influential people. He had a brilliant and caustic wit and he could not resist using that wit to make jackasses -- and therefore bitter enemies -- of those who disagreed with him. Even as a college student, he had been nicknamed "the wrangler" because of his argumentativeness and nonconformity. He even refused to wear academic robes, though this cost him several fines. Besides he was so brilliant a lecturer that students flocked to hear him, coming in numbers as high as two thousand, according to a possibly exaggerated report, while his colleagues mumbled away in empty halls, and nothing will infuriate colleagues more than that. In Padua, Galileo was corresponding with Kepler, and in this correspondence he admitted, as early as 1597, that he had come to believe in the theories of Copernicus, though he prudently refrained for a while from saying so publicly. The execution of Giordano Bruno in 1600 must have encouraged Galileo to continue refraining. In 1609, however, he heard that a magnifying tube, making use of lenses, had been invented in Holland. Before six months had passed, Galileo had devised his own version of the instrument, one that had a magnifying power of thirty-two. He could adjust it in reverse, to serve as a microscope, and he observed insects by this means. However, it was as a telescope that he made best use of it. He turned it on the heavens. Thus began the age of telescopic astronomy. Using his telescope Galileo found that the moon had mountains and the sun had spots, which showed once again that Aristotle was wrong in his thesis that the heavens were perfect and that only on earth was there irregularity and disorder. Tycho Brahe had already done that in his studies on his nova and his comet, and David Fabricius had done it in his studies of a variable star, but Galileo's findings attacked the sun itself. Other astronomers discovered the sunspots at almost the same time as Galileo -- for indeed, very large spots can sometimes be made out with the naked eyes of those foolish enough to stare at the sun -- and there was wrangling over priority, which made Galileo additional enemies. Galileo, however, whether he had priority in the discovery or not, did more than merely see the spots. He used them to show that the sun rotated about its axis in twenty-seven days, by following individual spots around the sun. He even determined the orientation of the sun's axis in that fashion. Nor did Galileo get off scot-free. His studies of the sun damaged his eyes, which had already suffered from infections in his youth, and in old age he went blind. The stars, even the bright ones, remained mere dots of light in the telescope, while the planets showed as little globes. Galileo deduced from this that the stars must be much farther away than the planets and that the universe might be indefinitely large. He also found that there we many stars in existence that could be seen by telescope but not by naked eye. The Milky Way itself owed its luminosity to the fact that it was composed of myriads of such stars. More dramatically, he found that Jupiter was attended by four subsidiary bodies, visible only by telescope, that circled it regularly. Within a few weeks of observation he was able to work out the periods of each. Kepler gave these latter bodies the name of satellites and they are still known as the Galilean satellites. They are known singly by the mythological names of Io, Europa, Ganymede, and Callisto. Jupiter with its satellites was a model of a Copernican system -- small bodies circling a large one. It was definite proof that not all astronomical bodies circled the earth. Galileo observed that Venus showed phases entirely like those of the moon from full to crescent, which it must do if the Copernican theory was correct. According to the Ptolemaic theory Venus would have to be a perpetual crescent. The discovery of the phases of Venus definitely demonstrated, by the way, the fact that planets shine by reflected sunlight. Galileo discovered that the night side (that is, the dark portion) of the moon when the moon was less than full had a dim glow, which he explained as caused by light shining upon it from Earth ("earthshine"). It had been seen before but had been explained otherwise. Poseidonius thought it was sunlight shining through a partly transparent moon. Reinhold thought the moon's surface was phosphorescent. Earthshine showed that Earth like the planets, gleamed in the Sun, and removed one more point of difference between Earth and the heavenly bodies. All these telescopic discoveries meant the final establishment of Copernicanism more than half a century after Copernicus had published his book. Galileo announced his discoveries in special numbers of a periodical he called Siderus Nuncius ("Starry Messenger") and these aroused both great enthusiasm and profound anger. Aged Venetian aristocrats clambered to the top of a tower in order to look through one of his telescopes and see ships, otherwise invisible, far out at sea. He was the best lensmaker in Europe at the time and built a number of telescopes. He sent them all over Europe (one reaching Kepler) so that others might confirm his findings. Both Venice and Florence offered him lucrative positions. To the annoyance of the Venetians, Galileo chose to travel to his beloved Florence. Galileo visited Rome in 1611, where he was greeted with honor and delight, though not everyone was happy. The thought of imperfect heavens, of invisible objects shining there, and, worst of all, of the Copernican system enthroned and Earth demoted from its position as center of the universe was most unsettling. Galileo also rather unwisely ventured to write a book giving his views on the bible and generally discussing theological subjects to the offense of theologians. Galileo's conservative opponents persuaded Pope Pius V to declare Copernicanism a heresy, and Galileo was forced into silence in 1616. Intrigue continued. Now Galileo's friends, now his enemies seemed to have gained predominance. In 1632 Galileo was somehow persuaded that the Pope then reigning (Urban VIII) was friendly and would let him speak out. He therefore published his masterpiece, Dialogue on the Two Chief World Systems, in which he had two people, one representing the view of Ptolemy and other the view of Copernicus, present their arguments before an intelligent layman. Amazingly enough, despite his long friendship with Kepler, Galileo did not mention Kepler's modification of Copernicus' theory, a modification which improved it beyond measure -- but then, Kepler's work was appreciated by virtually no one at the time. Galileo of course gave the Copernican the brilliant best of the battle. The Pope was persuaded that Simplico, the character who upheld the views of Ptolemy in the book, was a deliberate and insulting caricature of himself. The book was all the more damaging to those who felt themselves insulted, because it was written in vigorous Italian for the general public (and not merely for the Latin-learned scholars) and was quickly translated into other languages -- including Chinese! Galileo was brought before the Inquisition on charges of heresy (his indiscreet public statements made it easy to substantiate the charge) and on June 22, 1633, was forced to renounce any views that were at variance with the Ptolemaic system. Romance might have required a heroic refusal to capitulate, but Galileo was nearly seventy and he had the example of Bruno to urge him to caution. He recanted and was condemned to a penance of psalm recitations each week for three years -- and, of course, to refrain from further heresy. Legend has it that when he rose from his knees, having completed his renunciation, he muttered "Eppur si muove!" ("And yet it moves," referring to Earth.) This was indeed the verdict given by the world of scholarship, and the silencing of Galileo for the remaining few years of his old age (during which -- in 1637 -- he made his last astronomical discovery, that of the slow swaying or "libration" of the moon as it revolves) was an empty victory for the conservatives. When he died they won an even shallower victory by refusing him burial in consecrated ground. The Scientific Revolution begun with Copernicus had been opposed for nearly a century at the time of Galileo's trial, but by then the fight was lost. The Revolution not only existed, but had prevailed, although, to be sure, there remained pockets of resistance. Harvard, in the year of its founding (1636), remained firmly committed to the Ptolemaic theory. Galileo's Dialogue was not removed from the Catholic "Index of Prohibited Books" until 1835. In 1965, Pope Paul VI, on a visit to Pisa, spoke highly of Galileo -- an even clearer admission that on this issue the Church had been in the wrong. Galileo was truly a revolutionary, but his revolution was not his advances in mathematics, instrumentation, nor in his experiments. His revolution consisted in elevating "induction" above deduction as the logical method of science. Instead of building conclusions on an assumed set of generalizations, the inductive method starts with observations. The careful and precise recording of these observations leads to giving names to the things observed. Names are given to the "observables" and various methods are used to manipulate them to find correlations between what is observed. Mathematics is a powerful tool of logic, but not the only one, for finding these correlations. In the next step, generalizations are derived from the coorelated data from observations. Of course, even the Greeks obtained their axioms from observation; Euclid's axiom that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points was an intuitive judgment based on experience. But whereas the Greek philosopher minimized the role played by induction, the modern scientist looks on induction as the essential process of gaining knowledge, the only way of justifying generalizations. Moreover, the scientist realizes that no generalization can be allowed to stand unless it is repeatedly tested by newer and still newer experiments -- the continuing test of further induction. Lacking sufficient proof, the mechanical concept of the universe was at that time mostly a creed that echoed the Archimedean motto in a mechanistic phrasing, "give me matter and motion and I will construct the universe." Such a program undoubtedly rested on tremendous convictions if not extraordinary ambitions. The clinching proofs of the mechanical philosophy were still far away. Little if any had yet been realized of the great promise of the mechanical creed, namely, the prediction by mathematics of all future events that were to take place in the physical universe. Ambitious programs had, of course, been given publicity by their authors. Galileo, making the most of the extraordinary impact of his Starry Messenger, wrote at length to the secretary of state of the Tuscan court, Belisario Vinta, about his scientific program that was centered on mechanics. As the letter stated, Galileo planned "three books on local motion...three books on mechanics, two relating to demonstrations of its principles, and one concerning its problems." Actually, of all his contemporaries, he alone lived up to the boastful self-appraisal so fashionable in his day:Though other men have written on this subject what has been is not one-quarter of what I write, either in quantity or otherwise. [Note 2].The Mechanics of Galileo, printed in 1634 on Mersenne's order, fell far short of this goal. What was to become Galileo's decisive contribution to mechanics had emerged from his studies on local motion. The Discourses on Two New Sciences intimated for the first time what a book on physics ought to be: a sober, mathematical analysis of experiments followed by deductions. Partial as was Galileo's achievement in mechanics, what he produced was a foundation on which following generations securely built. This was not the case with most of Descartes' dicta in physics. In fact, as W. Whewell put it long ago:
Of the mechanical truths which were easily attainable in the begriming of the seventeenth century, Galileo took hold of as many, and Descartes of as few, as was well possible for a man of genius. [Note 3].The reason for this rested no doubt on Descartes' unbounded faith in his own version of mechanics that, while expressing well some basic points, glossed readily over details. In his physical universe there were only bodies and motion, and he restricted, at least in principle, his ambitious program of physics to the consideration of an "infinity of motions that last forever in the world." [Note 4] of the quantity of the total sum of these motions he clearly stated that it could not be diminished or lost. [Note 5] Furthermore, in a passage that in spite of its brevity strikingly anticipates the image of the all-knowing spirit described by Laplace, he argued that "if somebody were to know perfectly what are the small particles of all bodies and what are their movements and their relative positions, he would perfectly know the whole nature." [Note 6]. Also, it must be admitted that his writings on physics were in full conformity with his basic tenet rejecting firmly the major preoccupation of organismic physics -- the interpretation of physical processes and laws in terms of teleology. "We shall adopt," he wrote, "no opinions whatever about the goals that either God or nature might have set for themselves in producing the things of nature, because we should not arrogantly claim to be privy to their counsels." [Note 8]. This would have been the correct explanation of the differences between rules and observed facts had the experiments been carried out in such a way as to approximate gradually the ideal case with the elimination of disturbing factors, such as resistance. Descartes' faith in mechanism, however, had too many a priori features to permit him to see the crucial need in physics of approximating on the experimental level the ideal conditions in which certain physical phenomena might take place. Consequently, Descartes' mechanistic explanations did not always have enough respect for the actual way things happened. Explaining the refraction of light by analogy with bouncing balls, Descartes satisfied only the shibboleths of mechanism by using the figure of a hefty tennis player in the illustration of the problem in his La Dioptrique [Note 9]; the ball, supposedly having a lesser velocity in the denser medium, was shown as following a path bending away from the normal instead of getting closer to it. Had Descartes experimented with tennis balls he would probably have realized that he should look somewhere else for an illustration of his law. Not being an experimenter, he failed to perceive the irony of the situation into which his "absolute truths" had led him. But he had less trust in the facts than in the tenets of his mechanical philosophy, or rather creed, which prescribed that little if any reliance "should be placed upon observations that are not supported by true reasons." [Note 10]. The result was a strange imbalance between evidences and "principles" which comes to light nowhere better than in the manner in which Descartes criticized the experiments of others, and those of Galileo in particular. While praising him for his emphasis on mathematics, Descartes took Galileo to task for his attention to particular cases "without having considered the first causes of nature." According to Descartes' sweeping judgment, Galileo "has built without a foundation. Indeed because his fashion of philosophizing is so near the truth one can the more readily recognize his faults." [Note 11] Needless to say the shoe was on the wrong foot. The Cartesians were no more fortunate when it came to the mathematical results of non-Cartesian physicists. The famous case is Galileo's law of the free fall, which neither Descartes nor Mersenne would accept. Mersenne's remark on this point is particularly characteristic, showing as it does the highly arbitrary character of some formulations of the mechanical creed in the first part of the seventeenth century. "I doubt that Signor Galileo performed the experiments of the inclined planes, because he makes no mention of them and because the proportion he gives often contradicts experience." [Note 12] True, Mersenne wished that as many as possible would perform the experiment and with all the necessary precautions to see "if enough light could be drawn from them for constructing a theory." [Note 13] This was a skeptical proviso, however, for Mersenne held that experiments were not able to give rise to a science. On the contrary, scientific knowledge was to be derived according to the Cartesians from postulates and "necessary conclusions" that were to be considered, to hear J. Rohault -- the most widely read expositor of Cartesian physics -- not as arbitrary hypotheses but rather as truths that "follow necessarily from the motion and division of the parts of the matter." This, he added, "experience teaches us to recognize in the universe." [Note 14] Such a halfhearted reference to the role of experience was genuinely Cartesian and Rohault probably did not even care to soften much the glaring arbitrariness of the dicta of the Cartesian version of mechanical philosophy. To claim too much, however, ultimately creates suspicion even within the fold. A Cartesian himself, Huygens could not help seeing some non-scientific motivation behind Descartes' contentions. That Descartes, as Huygens put it, was jealous of the fame of Galileo, and wanted to be revered in the schools as Aristotle had been was only too human and certainly forgivable. Descartes' absolute statements were, however, a different matter, for, as Huygens observed, science had to suffer the consequences. Descartes, he wrote, "put forward his conjectures as verities, almost as if they could be proved by his affirming them on oath...and claimed to have revealed the precise truth thereby greatly impeding the discovery of genuine knowledge." [Note 15] But whatever cracks and faults there might have been in Descartes' physics, of its basic assumptions, the mechanical explanation of the world, Huygens entertained no doubts. When speaking of the nature of light did Huygens not voice wholeheartedly the mechanical creed? For him the focusing of light by concave mirrors was "assuredly the mark of motion, at least in the true philosophy, in which one conceives the causes of all natural effects in terms of mechanical motions." There were no alternatives, for, as he exclaimed, "this we must necessarily do, or else renounce all hope of ever comprehending anything in physics." [Note 17] Far less skeptical than Huygens regarding things invisible, Boyle kept trying to give a metaphysical foundation to the mechanical creed all his life. He viewed the shape of the universe as a consequence of the motion and mechanical properties with which God had endowed the particles of matter in the beginning. On this fundamental tenet he based the mechanical philosophy that in his words, "teaches that the phenomena of the world are physically produced by the mechanical properties of the parts of matter, and that they operate upon one another according to mechanical laws." [Note 18] In Boyle's eyes the validity of these laws knew no exception. Even an angel, he said, could not produce any real change in the world without doing it through mechanical means. Not that this meant to impose a sort of constraint on celestial beings. As pure intelligences, the angels had to operate on extended matter along the only way that befitted correct reasoning: the mechanical way. For, as Boyle stressed, the mechanical philosopher can accept only such physical agents as intelligible which can be reduced "to matter and some or other of those only catholick affections of matter." [Note 19] Such emphasis on the exclusive intelligibility of the mechanical principles cannot be stressed enough if one is to have a genuine insight into the classical physicist's state of mind. This holds of Kelvin's age as well as of Boyle's. Not that Boyle had been the initiator of the conviction that equated intelligibility with mechanism: his excellence lay rather in his ability to serve as the literary spokesman of the scientific aspirations of his age. For Boyle, prolific as his writings were, did not say much that was new. Yet, in all that he said his contemporaries instinctively recognized their own minds and tastes. As Leibniz commented on Boyle's works in 1691: "In his books, and for all the consequences that he draws from his observations, he concludes only what we all know, namely, that everything happens mechanically." [Note 20] Leibniz was not alone in such an appraisal of Boyle's efforts. He also recalled with unreserved concurrence the puzzlement of Spinoza, who, as Leibniz tells us, was unable to comprehend why Boyle had not derived "from an infinity of beautiful experiments" conclusions other than the one "which could have been taken as a principle, namely, that everything in nature is effected mechanically; a principle which can be made certain by reason alone and never by experiments however numerous they may be." [Note 21] Leibniz was, of course, the prince of those who during this early phase of classical physics gave precedence to the a priori approach as opposed to a rigorous inductive, experimental procedure. This choice of theirs, however, did not set them apart from people like Hooke and Boyle, as regards that basic tenet which equated intelligibility with mechanism. The mechanistic physics had to be content, for a while at least, to emphasize the principal point: all genuine explanations in physics had to be molded on some mechanical pattern. The details of the pattern were of secondary importance provided they were strictly mechanical. Thus, in explaining the behavior of air in a pump, Boyle spoke of the spring of air without committing himself to either of the two mechanical models applicable to the problem. [Note 22] The air, he said, might resemble a heap of little bodies lying upon one another like a fleece of wool, or it might just as well be a mass of flexible particles agitated by heat. If the latter is the case, the particles of air would have no "structure requisite to springs," still the principle of mechanical explanation is safeguarded, for what is a chain of impacts if not a form of mechanism? A rapid glance at the titles of Boyle's works shows that in most of the topics he investigated the exact mechanism of the processes responsible for the phenomena could not be known in Boyle's time. All the same, Boyle spoke undauntedly of the mechanical causation of all the phenomena perceived by the senses. [Note 23] In the world of phenomena hardly anything missed his attention, and he recounted with untiring patience an immense list of observations and experiments relating to the mechanical production of heat, cold, tastes, odors volatility, corrosiveness, chemical precipitation, magnetism, and electricity, to name his main topics alone. [Note 24] True, Boyle was aware of the fact that the gross mechanical processes he spoke of were only in distant relation to the basic mechanism of nature operating through the most minute parts of bodies. What this mechanism was like one could only infer by imagination, helped in no small measure by those recently devised "outward instruments" as Hooke called the telescope and the microscope. Machinery, or miniature clockwork, was seen neither by Hooke nor by others peering through the microscope, but they saw enough small geometrical patterns in a wide range of materials investigated. They hardly asked for more on behalf of their faith in mechanism. As Hooke, the most celebrated early reporter on the world of the microscope, put it: "Those effects of Bodies, which have been commonly attributed to Qualities, and those confess'd to be occult, are perform'd by the small Machines of Nature...[and] are...the mere products of Motion, Figure and Magnitude." [Note 25] In all this, however, the rhetoric of conviction was far ahead of the sober appraisal of the evidence at hand. Little did this disparity between claims and proofs worry his contemporaries. Instead, they praised such efforts unreservedly, as Locke did in speaking of Boyle: "He was thought to go farthest in an intelligible explanation of the qualities of bodies." [Note 26] (italics added).
June twenty second sixteen thirty three, A momentous date for you and me. Of all the days that was the one An age of reason could have begun.
Again the garden of the Florentine Ambassador at Rome where Galileo's assistants wait the news of the trial. The Little Monk and Federzoni are attempting to concentrate on a game of chess. Virginia kneels in a corner, praying and counting her beads.
I, Galileo Galilei, son of the late Vincenzo Galilei, Florentine, aged seventy years, arraigned personally before this tribunal, and kneeling before you, most Eminent and Reverend Lord Cardinals, Inquisitors general against heretical depravity throughout the whole Christian Republic, having before my eyes and touching with my hands, the holy Gospels -- swear that I have always believed, do now believe, and by God's help will for the future believe, all that is held, preached, and taught by the Holy Catholic and Apostolic Roman Church. But whereas -- after an injunction had been judicially intimated to me by this Holy Office, to the effect that I must altogether abandon the false opinion that the sun is the centre of the world and immovable, and that the earth is not the centre of the world, and moves, and that I must hold, defend, or teach in any way whatsoever, verbally or in writing, the said doctrine, and after it had been notified to me that the said doctrine was contrary to Holy Scripture -- I wrote and printed a book in which I discuss this doctrine already condemned, and adduce arguments of great cogency in its favor, without presenting any solution of these; and for this cause I have been pronounced by the Holy Office to be vehemently suspected of heresy, that is to say, of having held and believed that the sun is the centre of the world and immovable, and that the earth is not the centre and moves: Therefore, desiring to remove from the minds of your Eminences, and of all faithful Christians, this strong suspicion, reasonably conceived against me, with sincere heart and unfeigned faith I abjure, curse, and detest the aforesaid errors and heresies, and generally every other error and sect whatsoever contrary to the said Holy Church; and I swear that in the future I will never again say or assert, verbally or in writing, anything that might furnish occasion for a similar suspicion regarding me; but that should I know any heretic, or person suspected of heresy, I will denounce him to this Holy Office, or to the Inquisitor and ordinary of the place where I may be. Further, I swear and promise to fulfill and observe in their integrity all penances that have been, or that shall be, imposed upon me by this Holy Office. And, in the event of my contravening, (which God forbid) any of these my promises, protestations, and oaths, I submit myself to all the pains and penalties imposed and promulgated in the sacred canons and other constitutions, general and particular, against such delinquents. So help me God, and these His holy Gospels, which I touch with my hands. I, the said Galileo Galilei, have abjured, sworn, promised, and bound myself as above; and in witness of the truth thereof I have with my own hand subscribed the present document of my abjuration, and recited it word for word at Rome, in the Convent of Minerva, this twenty-second day of June, 1633. I, Galileo Galilei, have abjured as above with my own hand.
For a great WWW access provider contact Grady Associates at http://www.rochester.ny.us/Grady.html Fred L. Wilson (FLWGSH@ritvax.isc.rit.edu)