Original Source
..
Complementarity and the Uncertainty Principle
The third section of the Como paper deals with how complementarity resolves
the apparent paradox of the uncertainty relationship. Since these relations
express the crux of the non-classical aspect of quantum theory, understanding
them through complementarity will improve our appreciation of Bohr's point of
view.
..
Bohr's analysis was essentially coeval with Heisenberg's discovery, but he
never intended complementarity as merely an explanation of the uncertainty
principle. Einstein's criticisms forced Bohr repeatedly into an analysis of
experimental situations designed to overcome the limits of the principle.
Thus, in the years following the Como paper, Bohr's original approach from an
analysis of the application of the classical modes of description was largely
lost from sight.
..
The belief that Bohr designed complementarity simply as his analysis of the
uncertainty principle is historically unfounded, but it is a natural mistake,
for he was anxious to show how complementarity explains the uncertainty
principle. For physicists raised in the framework of classical physics, the
discovery of the uncertainty principle was a stunning surprise. Thus it is
hardly remarkable that in speaking to a group of physicists at Como, Italy,
Bohr was very eager to show how his new framework of complementarity was able
to interpret this principle.
..
As Bohr understood it, both his complementarity and Heisenberg's uncertainty
principle were the consequences of the quantum postulate. Complementarity was
the consequence for a conceptual framework in which phenomena are described,
while Heisenberg's discovery was its formal mathematical consequence. In
quantum mechanical formalism, these parameters are not independent of each
other, but are linked reciprocally by the measure of discontinuity in change
of state symbolized by Planck's constant.
..
It follows mathematically from uncertainty relations that the classical
formalism can only be defined within limits fixed by the element of
discontinuity involved in the change of state of a quantum system. Since the
initial conditions cannot be defined beyond this point, theoretical
predictions of the future state of the system are "indeterministic" or
probabilistic in nature. However, Bohr believed that even though the
uncertainty principle was logically entailed by the quantum postulate, the
formalism itself could not tell us whether this limitation was merely a limit
on knowledge or if it reflects a deeper ontological "indeterminacy".
..
Nevertheless, classical formalism must be regarded as a special case of
statistical determinism in which the statistical spread of determinism is
negligible relative to the precision of the measurement. Since these are in
fact the sort of interactions which are described classically (in line with
Bohr's correspondence principle) the predictions quantum mechanics make will
approach those of classical mechanics as the exchange of energy or momentum
involved in the exchange increases in size relative to that expressed by
Planck's constant. In other words, as we deal with larger and larger objects,
statistical determinacy will converge to strict determinism.
..
Statistical predictions in quantum mechanics might be interpreted as
predictions describing behavior between large collections of atomic systems,
each of which can be described by as yet undiscovered deterministic laws. In
fact, the statistical spread of the formalism can only be confirmed by
measurements on many atomic systems. Bohr categorically rejected this
interpretation, however. He writes:
One might perhaps believe that the properties of the elements do not inform us
directly of the behavior of individual atoms but, rather, that we are always
concerned only with statistical regularities holding for the average
conditions of a large number of atoms. ...The elements have, however, other
properties which permit of more direct conclusions being drawn with respect to
the states of motion of the atomic constituents. Above all, we must assume
that the quality of the light which the elements in certain circumstances emit
and which is characteristic of each element is essentially determined by what
occurs in a single atom. Niels Bohr, The Atomic Theory
..
Bohr proposed the quantum postulate to develop a mechanics which would
represent atomic systems as mechanically stable. This property of stability
must be attributed to each individual atom, thus the quantum postulate
expresses a fact about the behavior of individual atomic systems. Since the
postulate entails the statistical nature of the predictions of the formalism,
the loss of determinism must be a consequence of the behavior of individual
atoms. Thus Bohr declares as "vain the...
..
...repeated, expressed hopes of avoiding the essentially statistical character
of quantum mechanical description by the assumption of some causal mechanism
underlying the atomic phenomena and hitherto inaccessible to
observation... Above all such hopes would seem to rest upon an underestimate of
the fundamental differences between the laws with which we are concerned in
atomic physics and the everyday experiences which are comprehended so
completely by the ideas of classical physics...the peculiar stability
properties of atomic structures which are in obvious contrast with the
properties of any mechanical model, but which are so intrinsically connected
with the existence of the quantum of action, form the very condition for the
existence of the objects and measuring instruments, with the behavior of which
classical physics is concerned. Letter From Bohr to John Slater
..
Different Interpretations of the Uncertainty Principle
The difficulty many philosophers and physicists have with indeterminism makes
it easy to misinterpret what Bohr was trying to say. To him, indeterminism was
a theoretical reflection of a fundamental fact about the behavior of
individual atoms. Heisenberg's discovery of the uncertainty principle in 1927
was no surprise for Bohr, as it was for most other physicists of the time. His
whole orientation had prepared him for just such a revolution.
..
Before going into Bohr's analysis of the uncertainty principle, two points
should be made clear. First, the mathematical formalism expressing
relationships encompassed by the "uncertainty principle" are straight forward
deductive consequences of the quantum postulate. All too often, discussions of
the principle begin with a series of thought experiments intended to
demonstrate that observations which determine the value of one observable
within a certain range require physical conditions which preclude determining
its canonically conjugate observable within a range that would contradict the
uncertainty principle.
..
It is then easy to get the mistaken impression that the principle expresses an
empirical generalization derived from analyzing physical situations and that
such a presumed empirical discovery is then injected as a postulate into the
theoretical formalism. However, this is not the case. Heisenberg first
developed his formalism for theoretical representation of the atomic system
processes, and then showed that the consequence of his formalism was that the
system could not be characterized by a state which was defined in terms of
precise values for both canonically conjugate parameters. Since this analysis
of complementarity doesn't require studying the mathematical formalism, there
is no need to consider the derivation of the principle itself. The concern
here is to give Bohr's theoretical conclusions some physical significance.
..
Heisenberg's Interpretation
Heisenberg was led to his discovery by proposing that "nature allowed only
experimental situations to occur which could be described within the framework
of the formalism of quantum mechanics". In considering various thought
experiments, he, and later Bohr, tried to show it was impossible to determine
with arbitrary precision the values of both of the canonically conjugate
observables. The reason for this is notoriously ambiguous in Heisenberg's own
presentations, however.
..
In some cases, he seems to imply that uncertainty arises because the
observation "disturbs" the experiment. In this case, observation would require
interaction, and the uncertainty arises there. However, interactions do not
arise continually in atomic systems, therefore this interpretation must accept
the classical presumption that all physical systems exist in well-defined
states theoretically represented by the concept of the classical state. Here
it is meaningful to talk about the classical state of the quantum system, even
though we cannot precisely know the parameters that define any particular
state.
..
The Verificationist Viewpoint
However, in other cases, Heisenberg seems to imply a more "verificationist"
view that since it's impossible to verify empirical statements for atomic
systems, assertions making use of this concept are meaningless. He comments:
Any use of the words "position" and "velocity" with an accuracy exceeding that
given by [the uncertainty principle] is just as meaningless as the use of
words whose sense is not defined...one should remember that the human language
permits the construction of sentences which do not involve any consequences
and which therefore have no content at all - in spite of the fact that these
sentences produce some kind of picture in our imagination... one should be
especially careful in using the words "reality", "actuality", etc., since
these words very often lead to statements of the type just mentioned. From
Heisenberg interviews
..
The verificationist view is associated with the logical positivist view, which
we have already seen was pervasive during that time. It is worth noting a
rather obvious inconsistency in the same work from which the above passage was
quoted, Heisenberg seems to make a claim about what the electron "really" is.
Looking at how Bohr approached this same problem, it's easy to see how
different his thinking was.
..
How Bohr Saw Heisenberg's Discovery as Complementarity
Typically the two parameters involved in the uncertainty principle are of
position and momentum, or of energy and time. Bohr saw Heisenberg's discovery
from the point of view of the complementarity of the two classical modes of
description. Bohr saw the determination of position or time as the goal of the
mode of space-time coordination, while seeing the determination of momentum or
energy as a goal of applying the "claim of causality" through the conservation
principles. Just as the uncertainty principle allows one to determine position
and time or momentum and energy with an arbitrary degree of precision, so the
two classical modes could be used together, but only in a complementary way.
..
From Bohr's point of view, the uncertainty principle does not express any
consequence of "disturbing" the system by observation. But at the same time,
his analysis does depend on recognizing that observation involves an
interaction that is "uncontrollable" once the quantum postulate is accepted.
Bohr tried to show that the classical state of the system is only attainable
by assuming it is possible to apply both spatial-temporal and causal modes of
description to the system at the same time. Since the quantum postulate
expressly says this cannot be done, the classical concept of the atomic system
is no longer defined. For this reason, the disturbance principle is at odds
with the analysis of the uncertainty principle from the view of
complementarity.
..
In fact, Bohr already arrived at the need for a complementary point of view
before he knew of the uncertainty principle, but quite naturally saw
Heisenberg's discovery as confirmation of his own analysis. He even considered
using the word "reciprocal" (derived from the mathematical way of expressing
the uncertainty principle between the canonically conjugate parameters)
instead of "complementary" to refer to the two modes of description.
The Disturbance Principle
..
Though it forms no part of complementarity, the disturbance principle was
frequently defended as part of the Copenhagen Interpretation and often
identified with Bohr's view in the years following Heisenberg's discovery.
From the perspective of Heisenberg, it appeared that the basis of the
disturbance principle lay in the fact that the instruments doing the observing
"disturbed" the observed system such that its state after observation is no
longer what was determined in the measurement. This interpretation compares
observation of atomic systems to measuring, for example, the inner workings of
a wrist watch using a yardstick.
..
However, the disturbance interpretation plays havoc with the facts behind the
genesis of the uncertainty principle and its status within the mathematical
formalism of quantum mechanics. The principle is a straight forward deductive
consequence of the quantum theoretical formalism which provides a highly
confirmed means of predicting the outcome of interaction between radiation and
matter. There is no mention of disturbance in the derivation of the principle
itself, nor of how to go about determining the relevant parameters.
..
The design of experiments is relevant only to interpreting the physical
significance of the principle. The assumption that the classical system really
exists in a classical mechanical state supposes the question of whether an
experiment could be designed which will yield greater knowledge about the
state of the atomic system than the uncertainty principle allows. If this
could be done, the theory would be properly judged incomplete.
The disturbance interpretation mistake becomes apparent when we realize, that
according to it, we could only approach classical ideals of strict determinism
if our measuring instruments were the size of atoms. However, it is only an
immense difference between the dimensions of ordinary human experience and
those involved in atomic processes that made strict determinism a nearly
obtainable goal. If our instruments were the same size as atoms, then the role
of the quantum in an interaction would be ever increasing rather than
decreasing, as the disturbance interpretation suggest.
..
In classical mechanics, the observation also "disturbs" the observed, but the
disturbance is either negligible or "controllable" and so can be accounted for
in defining the state of an isolated system after the observation interaction.
In quantum theory, ordinarily the effect of the interaction cannot be
considered negligible nor "controllable". Since the disturbance interpretation
makes it appear that the uncertainty principle is a empirical generalization,
it's unable to explain why this alleged disturbance cannot be determined in
the quantum framework, and allows a return to classical deterministic
formalism.
..
The Epistemic Interpretation
A second possible interpretation, the "epistemic interpretation", holds that
the uncertainty principle is a consequence that it was developed to describe
not the properties of atomic systems, but rather what we can know about nature
as we experience it. If we accept that the adequacy of a theory rests on its
success in predicting observable phenomena, then the uncertainty principle
gives no reason to hold that quantum theory is inadequate. The theory is in no
way incomplete because it allows only either a measurement on position and
time, or momentum and energy, because in fact no phenomena allows us to
determine such information. The uncertainty principle merely expresses this
fact and warrants accepting it as a mathematical instrument for predicting
relevant phenomena.
..
The epistemic interpretation may have been motivated by talk that properties
of a transphenomenal nature is meaningless and irrelevant to science.
Classically, the notion of an independent reality "existing" apart from its
phenomenal manifestation could be regarded as that concept of an isolated
system. Since classical formalism describes the motions of particles and
waves, the reality we experience should be consistent regarding such particles
and waves. However, what quantum theory tells us is that if its description of
its atomic systems is considered complete, since it cannot define a classical
mechanical state for these systems, they cannot be considered particles or
waves. It follows that the notion of an independent reality cannot be
described as previously thought from the classical viewpoint.
..
While the concept of an independently existing reality can no longer be
assumed to be describable, it doesn't necessarily follow that this concept of
an independent reality bears no relation to the world as experienced or as
described in scientific theory. However, if the epistemic interpretation
cannot establish that the notion of an independently existing reality is
meaningless, how does it justify its claim that our knowledge is limited in
the way expressed by the uncertainty principle?
..
On one hand, if the meaningfulness of any claims concerning the character of
an independent reality is denied, then it cannot be said the reason we cannot
know, for example, the simultaneous position and momentum of a particle is
because in reality there are no properties to be known. But if there is no
such reason for the conclusions of the uncertainty principle, why not instead
conclude that an altogether different theoretical formalism will one day be
invented to escape these limitations and return to strict determinism?
..
On the other hand, if the possibility of describing an independently existing
reality is allowed, then the theory is complete in providing everything that
can be known about such objects. The fact that there are limitations on how we
precisely determine the parameters is a consequence of a deeper limitation on
what it is that we can actually know. In this interpretation, the fact that
nature has thus far hidden from us any means of simultaneously determining
position and momentum of a particle may be revealed as only a limitation on
our imagination, with deeper mysteries lurking underneath that.
..
Either way, the epistemic interpretation cannot be made consistent with Bohr's
claim that quantum theory is complete without admitting that the limitation on
knowledge expressed by the uncertainty principle results from a character of a
reality behind the phenomena. If it is accepted, as is the classical
viewpoint, that parameters do correspond to properties of an independent
reality, since quantum theory uses such parameters implies that nature
possesses the corresponding properties. The proper conclusion would then be
that quantum theory is indeed incomplete and that one day we will find a
complete one.
..
Einstein and Bohr
Einstein seemed to think Bohr was defending the epistemic interpretation with
his framework of complementarity. By this time, Einstein had totally
repudiated the view that science is only concerned about developing a formal
means for predicting phenomena. This is the reason he repeatedly attempted to
devise thought experiments which would reveal more about the system than the
quantum formalism would permit, thereby dis-proving Bohr's belief it was
complete. In fact, if Bohr had defended the epistemic interpretation of the
uncertainty principle, as Einstein believed, Einstein's attitude would have
expressed open-minded characteristics of scientific progress while Bohr would
be seen as dogmatic.
..
Bohr's Interpretation of the Uncertainty Principle
Finally, let's turn to Bohr's interpretation of the uncertainty principle. He
writes According to the quantum theory, just the impossibility of neglecting
the interaction with the agency of measurement means that every observation
introduces a new uncontrollable element. Indeed, it follows from the above
considerations that the measurement of the positional co-ordinates of a
particle is accompanied not only by a finite change in the dynamic variables,
but also the fixation of its position means a complete rupture in the causal
description of its dynamical behavior, while the determination of its momentum
always implies a gap in the knowledge of its spatial propagation. Just this
situation brings out most strikingly the complementary character of the
description of atomic phenomena which appears as an inevitable consequence of
the contrast between the quantum postulate and the distinction between object
and agency of measurement. Como Lecture
..
In his debates with Heisenberg, Bohr would insist that in order for the
theoretical representation of the physical system to have any empirical
content at all, it must be possible to derive from it a description of the
observed phenomena, treated as a causal result of the behavior of the atomic
system. To give classical terms the empirical reference they must have
requires interacting with the system, however. But the quantum postulate
states that the interacting whole has an individuality which prohibits
unambiguously defining the state of the system while it is in observation.
..
Thus, the physical conditions necessary for observation are complementary to
those necessary for defining the state of the system. Bohr regarded the
uncertainty principle as directly expressing the formal consequence of this
complementarity between the mode of space time coordination and the mode of
causality description. Since the quantum postulate denies the classical
justification for regarding the parameters used to define the state as
pictures of the properties of an independent reality, Bohr repudiated the
classical correlation of the parameters with the properties of the object
regarded as isolated from any observed interaction. The "pictures" we can form
using these concepts of an isolated object refer not to a concrete reality
lying behind the phenomena, but to what Bohr called "abstractions":
..
On the whole, it would seem scarcely justifiable, in the case of the
interaction problem, to demand a visualization by means of space-time
pictures. In fact all our knowledge concerning the internal properties of
atoms is derived from experiments on their radiation and collision reactions
[i.e., on interactions], such that the interpretation of experimental facts
ultimately depends on the abstractions of radiation in free space and free
material particles [i.e., on systems as isolated]. Hence, our whole space-time
view of physical phenomena, as well as the definition of energy and momentum
depends ultimately on these abstractions. In judging the application of these
auxiliary ideas, we should only demand inner consistency, in which connection
special regard has been paid to the possibilities of definition and
observation. Como Lectures
..
The use of classical terms to describe atomic systems as "particles" or
"waves" interacting with the measuring apparatus refers not to a concrete
underlying reality, but to an abstraction which is necessary for describing
the phenomena as interactions between the measuring agencies and the physical
systems decried in quantum theory. Since the disturbance interpretation holds
that the objects of the atomic domain really do have properties corresponding
to the parameters that define their classical state, Bohr's interpretation is
that the limit expressed by the uncertainty principle is merely a consequence
of the formalism we must use to describe what it is we are observing.
..
Common Misunderstandings About Bohr's Viewpoint
Because we must still describe observations in terms of the classical
framework, it is easy to view the uncertainty principle as a limit on
knowledge. However, this misunderstanding is a consequence of presupposing
that the descriptive concepts of "particle" and "wave" picture the object to
which they refer as existing in isolation away from any observation. In other
words, we fail to make the quantum postulate a true postulate in our
description of nature. Consequently, we imagine somehow that the limitations
expressed by the postulate, and the uncertainty principle, are not inherent in
nature. And one day they will be circumvented when we gain improved empirical
information.
..
Bohr, on the other hand, argued against this classical tendency to interpret
the concepts as also referring unambiguously to an independent and real
object. He concluded that the concepts by which we express what we learn in an
observational interaction refer to properties of phenomenal objects which can
be described only in the interaction of the system with the observing
instruments. By recognizing the complementarity between space-time
coordination and causal description, Bohr avoided the dilemma that gives
trouble to the epistemic interpretation, since each phenomenal appearance is a
unique individual event.
..
Wave-particle dualism is not a feature of reality, but rather a feature of our
way of representing reality, and of course then the possibility is open for
different descriptions which may remove such a dualism. The fact that Bohr
emphatically believed such a search was futile reveals his conviction that
complementarity was a result of the very way we observe our reality.
As Bohr would say, "we must relearn the presuppositions governing the use of
our most elementary concepts". Complementarity tells us that since specific
parameters of a physical theory have empirical evidence only if interpreted as
referring to specific properties of observed phenomena, when those same
parameters are used to define the state of the system isolated from
observation, we cannot assume they can be interpreted as referring to
properties possessed by that system apart from observational interactions.
..
At the same time, the framework of complementarity cannot be coherent if it
ignores the question of how to refer to this "independent reality" which in
interacting with observational instruments produces the phenomena which are
described by the theory. Facing up to the epistemological and ontological
consequences concern the next two parts of this review. This ends Part 4 of
this review. Thanks for reading! Comments are appreciated!
..
The Framework of Complementarity
Part 1 - Overview Early Years Bohr Formulates Complementarity
Part 2 - Argument for Complementarity
Part 3 - Comments on Complementarity
Part 4 - Complementarity and the Uncertainty Principle
Part 5 - Refinement of Complementarity
Part 6 - Extension of Complementarity
Part 7 - The Nature of Empirical Knowledge
Part 8 - Complementarity and the Metaphysics of Quality